THE ECUMENICAL REVIEW – 1973 - JANUARY - pages
59 to 79
A lecture, transcribed from a recording, given at the Ecumenical Centre, Geneva, in
October 1972 on the occasion of an exhibition
of books and journals in French (see
Ecumenical Diary , below). ROGER GARAUDY is
Professor of Aesthetics in the University
of Poitiers, France. His books include From Anathema to Dialogue (English édition :
London, Collins and Co. and New York, Herder
and Herder, 1966) and L'Alternative
(Paris, Robert Laffont, 1972). The lecture was
translated from the French by the WCC
Language Service. The original is published in
the Bulletin du Centre Protestant d'Etudes,
Geneva, 1973.
II/ The premiss
of transcendence
As I said
just now, if the revolutionary outlook is not simply a reflection
of the
already existing world but the vision of a social order which does
not yet
exist, it follows — and this is a provisional statement of the
first
premiss I wish to discuss — that the goals of revolutionary action
cannot be
deduced simply from the past or the present. Man is always
something
other and something more than the sum of the conditions
which
have produced him. This is what distinguishes him from ail
other
kinds of animal. Otherwise we should be relegated to an existence
determined
solely by instinct. Echoing the Italian philosopher Vico,
Marx
pointed out in Das Kapital that man was not responsible for the
evolution
of nature but for his own history. Unlike natural evolution,
human
history is of man's making.
This
first premiss is no more than a premiss. We cannot here disguise
our
assumptions and claim that we are revolutionaries by some sort of
rational
argument or inescapable necessity. We posit the premiss that
it is
possible for us to liberate ourselves from a given natural order and
to shape
our own future. It is, if you like, a radical break with positivism.
Nothing
is more conservative than positivism. By confining
human
thought within the limits of the given, positivism necessarily
restricts
human action to the limits of the established order, unless some
vision or
plan emerges. If the empirical world of tangible data is selfcontained,
as the
eighteenth century French materialists believed, man
is left
with no room to make his own history. He is simply one element
in a purely
physical process. It was Kant's Critique which rescued us
from
precisely this impasse. The world of empirical experience is not
self-contained,
not self-sufficient. Contemporary epistemology appears
to
confirm this. Rejecting any naïve realism we have come to recognize
that
every proposition concerning nature, history, or God, is a human
utterance.
You can find this formula in Karl Barth applied to statements
about
God, but I believe it is indeed the basis of ail critical thought.
You can
find it in Kant, in Husserl and in Bachelard as well as in Barth.
Man's
activity is creative activity, not least when he thinks, when he
conceives
and elaborates possibilities, when he formulates hypotheses,
scientific
models, ideals, utopias and visions. This activity is part of
reality.
I believe
this to be one of the important ideas which we must hold to,
as
against the positivism of Hegel and Marx. The possible, provided
we do not
exclude man from it, is part of the real. Man must not be
arbitrarily
excluded from reality, as he is in positivism — for positivism
means not
only a world without God but also a world without man, a
world
from which man has been abstracted. But if man belongs to
reality,
then reality does not only consist of what already exists but also
of ail
that does not yet exist, ail that is still lacking, ail that can still
become.
As Fichte said long ago : 'The ideal is more real than the real.'
For the
real is itself fashioned in accordance with the possibilities which
our minds
conceive. If this possibility, this hypothesis, this vision, are
not
already written into the past or the present, if the future is more than
simply
the extrapolated extension of the past and the present, if something
new emerges,
then we are compelled to recognize this other dimension
of
reality, this constant possibility of surpassing the present, and
to
recognize this as the most normal fact of daily experience. To give
it its
proper name, transcendence is a fondamental dimension of
reality.
Transcendence
is the dimension of reality which cannot but appear when
man's
présence and créative activity are included in our definition of
reality.
I go so far as to say that transcendence is man's chief attribute
inasmuch
as he alone, unlike animals confined within the cycle of
repetitive
behaviour, is a being who can take stock of his purposes
beforehand
and by his efforts achieve something new.
This
transcendence is an everyday experience, present in every creative
act :
whether in the artist's creation, or in the research of the scientist
and
technologist, or in love, sacrifice, or revolution ; in everything, that
is to
say, where we break out of the circle of positivist knowledge and
rise
above purely utilitarian actions designed to satisfy needs that belong
to the
past.
If we
fail to give this dimension its full weight, we end up in some form
or other
of positivism ; the positivism of those who try to camouflage
their
assumptions. Some will tell us that reality consists only of 'chance
and
necessity'. Others will say that man is a puppet manipulated by the
'structures'.
In both cases there is a denial that man is a real factor in
reality.
I realize
that the term 'transcendence' poses certain problems, which
explain
why Marxists have often been reluctant to use it. One difficulty
in using
it is to avoid the irrational and supernatural connotations with
which it
has been loaded and, above ail, the dualistic images which it
suggests.
Certainly, if we are to use the word in a mature way, we cannot
entertain
a pre-critical conception of transcendence. In other words,
we must
never forget that what Barth said in a theological context is
also true
of nature and history, namely, that everything I say is a human
utterance.
This is
vital even from a practical standpoint. For once this element of
self-criticism
in ail human thinking is ignored, once we claim proprietary
rights
over reality so as to be able to declare what it is, once we
claim to
be the interpreter, the spokesman and even the agent of the
absolute,
we are on the direct road to the Inquisition or to Stalinism.
For these
are the logical and practical consequences of any assurance
that one
possesses complete and final truth. Thereafter, when confronted
with
people who disagree with us, we can only interpret this as evidence
of their
sickness or ill-will, for which the only remedy is the psychiatric
ward or
even the final exclusion of such people from society. Dogmatic
premisses
seem, indeed, to allow no other solution, whether in the
Church of
earlier centuries or more recently in Stalin's Russia.
A mature
concept of transcendence cannot overlook the, to my mind,
permanent
contribution of Marx's historical materialism. This may be
put very
simply by saying that Marx has taught us to look for the driving
force of
history within history itself. History is not made from outside,
neither
by a destiny such as Greek thought posited, nor by a providence
extrinsic
to human activity, nor by Hegel's 'absolute Spirit', nor by
progress
in the naïvely optimistic, eighteenth century sense, nor even in
the sense
of a dialectic of nature in which the human dialectic would
only be a
special instance of a general rule, as Stalin and his followers
—myself once included — believed.
—myself once included — believed.
Pre-Marxist
historians believed that history was ruled from outside.
Marx
explored the possibility that the driving force was within human
history,
arguing on the basis of the inertia of nature and the alienations
of
society, but also of the initiatives of men creating their own history.
We can
perhaps set alongside the dictum : 'Every statement made about
nature,
history, or God is a human utterance' a parallel dictum summarizing
Marx's
thought as follows : 'Everything which is done is done
by a
man.' This means that we are fully responsible for our own history ;
a point
of great practical consequence.